You are currently browsing the monthly archive for October 2008.

 

Hold the drawing of a face upside-down and you can’t tell the expression of the face. Perhaps you can see that it is smiling, but you won’t be able to say what sort of a smile it is. You wouldn’t be able to imitate the smile or describe its character more exactly.

And yet the upside-down picture may represent the object extremely accurately. (Wittgenstein, 1980a, §991) 

In one study of facial expression recognition by three people with congenital facial paralysis (Calder, A. J. et al., 2000), participants were asked to identify the emotion displayed in 10 examples of facial expressions associated with each of 6 basic emotions selected from the ‘Pictures of Facial Affect’ (Ekman and Friesen, 1976). In a second test computer-morphed facial expressions were used. Even when perceptual impairments were found, people with facial paralysis still perceived many of the facial expressions shown to them. This may suggest that the ability to produce facial expressions is not a necessary prerequisite of their recognition.

A difficulty with this study is the employment of prototypical, high intensity, still photographs as stimulus material. As noted above, such stimuli may in fact activate an automatic reaction due to their extremity that is not found for weaker non-prototypical expressions. And there is no evidence showing that this primitive response is inhibited in people with congenital facial paralysis. Using expressions that are not chosen according to their correspondence to an emotion stereotype is therefore an important consideration. To enhance ecological validity in studies of facial expression recognition in people with facial paralysis, dynamic facial expressions should be chosen. Like the drawing of an upside-down face, a static face may make it difficult to see clearly what expression the face expresses. Wittgenstein writes: 

A facial expression that was completely fixed couldn’t be a friendly one. Variability and irregularity are essential to a friendly expression. Irregularity is part of its physiognomy.

The importance we attach to the subtle shades of behavior. (Wittgenstein, 1980b, §§615-616)

References
Calder, A.J., Keane, J., Cole, J., Campbell, R., and Young, A.W. 2000. Facial expression recognition by people with mobius syndrome. Cognitive Neurospychology 17(1-3), 73-87. 

An overfull cup will spill its water when knocked or jarred. A person regularly given to some thought or other over time becomes saturated with it, and in it. He may even behave as though he is indistinguishable from his thought-patterns. When life tosses this individual about, as it does to all of us, he finds no place to which he may turn for solace. For all available niches have been accorded to his private obsession. Such a person may then spill over onto us and through others in a most negative and terrifying manner. Every person has a ‘saturation-point’. But, we all boil at different temperatures.

For a person to see light moving enchantlingly over a grass hill is to be drawn into a quality of intimacy to the perception such that the person is inclined to automatically imitate it. To see the hill as ‘enchanted’ is to take it as an interaction partner we mimic in speech, facial expressions, emotions, postures, gestures and mannerisms. Our reaction conveys rapport and understanding and leads to a desire to affiliate.

Wittgenstein noted that human beings adopt facial, postural and vocal behaviors that are congruent with the displays they perceive, and that these displays often represent mimicry. Social perception, understood by Wittgenstein as the ability to directly read off emotion and thought from a person’s behavior, has a direct effect on social behavior. As a result, we often do what we see others doing. How can a person see that the child wants to touch the dog, but doesn’t dare? Wittgenstein’s answer is that an observer ‘may also mimic a human being who would like to touch something, but doesn’t dare’ (Wittgenstein, 1980a, §1066). This suggests that mimicry is essential for understanding what the perceived behavior means. If a person could not do this, then he would fail to understand something important about what is expressed. The perception-behavior link Wittgenstein argues for is the human tendency to act in the same way as we see others act.

Wittgenstein considers as facial mimicry the congruent facial reactions to the emotional displays of others. Specifically, mimicry is understood as an expressive component. As facial mimicry is the direct consequence of perception, we do not need additional private mechanisms to engage in it. No introspection is required, nor a conscious decision. We just do it. For example, the difference between a friendly smile, a wry, sarcastic, ironic, or cruel smile may be no more than a minute difference (a thousandth of an inch) in the orientation of the facial features, but we perceive it, and not by measuring the difference. Moreover, we mimic such expressions without looking in the mirror, and without monitoring or checking the precise disposition of our features (Wittgenstein, 1958, §285). We see friendliness in a face; we do not infer it from such-and-such a facial configuration we know accompanies our own feelings: ‘We describe a face immediately as sad, radiant, bored, even when we are unable to give any other description of the features’ (Wittgenstein, 1980b, §570). The same can be said of facial mimicry: ‘One may also say: ‘He made this face’ or ‘His face altered like this‘, imitating it – and again one can’t describe it in any other way’ (Wittgenstein, 1980a, §920). There is something primitive about the ability to transpose what we perceive in the facial expression of someone else, to one’s own facial expression and activity. Indeed, one-month-old infants have been shown to smile, stick out their tongues, and open their mouths when they see someone else doing the same (Meltzoff & Moore, 1977).

However, facial mimicry may not always occur. An unsightly and unusual facial expression that leads to puzzlement or prejudice may not stimulate congruent facial expressions in an observer. Depending on the nature of the decoding task, facial reactions to emotional facial expressions may be either affective or cognitive. If we were to meet people who randomly mixed up posed and spontaneous emotional facial expressions, it is conceivable that ‘we should not know where we were within them’ (Wittgenstein, 1992, §201). And, if we had to decide whether an emotional facial expression was posed or spontaneous, no facial mimicry may accompany a cognitive judgment such as ‘I have no idea what is going on inside of them’. By contrast, Wittgenstein suggests that we may find facial mimicry when observers are asked to make affective judgments concerning emotional facial expressions.

In other cases, counter-mimicry may result. Wittgenstein imagines a face incapable of making gradual and subtle movements, and which had a limited number of facial expressions. When it altered, it would snap straight from one expression to another. He asks: ‘Would this fixed smile really be a smile? I might not be able to react as I do to a smile. Maybe it would not make me smile myself’ (Wittgenstein, 1980b, §614). This suggests that facial mimicry is not obligatory, and can be inhibited. Wittgenstein may have supported a conception of facial mimicry as ‘default social behavior’: we naturally mimic, as long as other considerations do not have a reason to intervene. For example, ‘a person who had seen only one facial expression couldn’t have the concept ‘facial expression’. ‘Facial expression’ exists only within a play of features’ (Wittgenstein, 1992, §766). This means that a person who had only seen ‘happy’ faces could not mimic them as happy. 

In sum, Wittgenstein acknowledges that observers mimic facial displays. However, the possibility of counter-mimicry he mentions may suggest that this reaction is somewhat less automatic and reflex-like than otherwise thought.

There are those of us who long for a superhuman intellect and to be as smart as the great thinkers. We tend to forget that ideas cost too. Genius that is the fruit of great industry may be too high a price to pay, especially when a demand is made for unremitting isolation from others.

The attraction of conspiracy theories is that they offer to explain what we fear may be only an act of random violence by an obscure malcontent.  They suggest a reason where there may be none. We are inclined to embrace fanciful lies rather than the tragedy of the ordinary. Just ask yourself: who was Lee Harvey Oswald?

Proposal for PhD Thesis in Philosophy

 Thesis Title: Pain 

This research project contributes to the study of pain with reference to Wittgenstein’s philosophical psychology and pain facial expression. The thesis divides into five papers as follows: 

– Paper 1: Pretence and the definition of pain (approx. 20,000 words)

– Paper 2: Primitive pain-expression and deliberate control (approx. 20,000 words)

– Paper 3: The indeterminacy of pain (approx. 20,000 words)

– Paper 4: Is there a pain face? (approx. 20,000 words)

– Paper 5: Moebius Syndrome and pain catastrophizing (approx. 20,000 words) 

A description of each paper is below. 

Paper 1: Pretence and the definition of pain

Description:

The International Association for the Study of Pain (IASP) Committee for Taxonomy defines pain as ‘an unpleasant sensory and emotional experience associated with actual or potential tissue damage, or described in terms of such damage’. They further state that ‘pain is always subjective. Each individual learns the application of the word through experiences related to injury in early life’ (Merskey, 1994).

This definition states that the employment of the word ‘pain’ needs to be learned through experiences in early life: a child has hurt himself and cries; and then adults talk to him and teach him the use (meaning) of ‘pain’. Wittgenstein (1958b) suggests that the child is trained to substitute its primitive, natural expressive pain-behavior first with exclamations and later with sentences such as ‘I have a stomach-ache’. There are other possibilities. One might point at someone who is manifestly in pain and say, ‘There: that is what it is to be in pain’, or ‘That is pain’ (see Wittgenstein, 1958b, §290). On the other hand, it appears that the perception of pain is an intrinsic feature of life itself, is manifested in all living organisms, and while subject to influence by life experiences, does not require previous experience in the first instance. The first experience of tissue injury is painful, in much the same way that touch, smell, vision, or hearing need not be learned in order to occur in the human being. Infants from 25 weeks gestation show a characteristic pain face consisting of eyes squeezed shut, brows lowered, deepening of the nasolabial furrow, open lips, with mouth stretched vertically and horizontally (Craig et al. 1993; Stevens et al., 1994).

The meaning of these sensations, however, will develop with experience through positive, negative, and contextual associations (Anand & Craig, 1996). In other words, learning cannot be separated from the behaving organism: ‘Only of living human being and what resembles (behaves like) a living human being can one say: it has sensations, it sees, is blind; is deaf; is conscious or unconscious’ (Wittgenstein, 1958, §218). As the person develops, so do its behavioral repertoire and the qualitative features of its subjective experiences. As characteristic features of the behaving organism, learning is incorporated into experience as components of a ‘form of life’ (Sullivan, 2001).

An adult, for example, can pretend to be in pain without saying a word, merely by facial expressions, torso movements, or paralinguistic qualities of speech (Wittgenstein, 1982, §944). But for these apparently simple behaviors to constitute pretence presupposes complex motives, intentions (e.g. the intention to deceive), as well as a complicated play of expressions (i.e. numerous nonverbal actions). Can one imagine a new-born child with the play of facial expressions and expressive-behavior of an adult? A new-born child cannot be insincere, but neither can he be sincere. To dissimulate pain, he must first learn to mimic and to intend to mimic (Wittgenstein, 1958b).

Available empirical evidence suggests that by the age of four children are able to use techniques to dissemble non-painful subjective states. This suggests that they may succeed in misrepresenting expressions of pain (Larochette et al., 2006). Cases of illness falsification have been reported in children as young as 8 years (Libow, 2000). Children report that their most common reason for using deception, especially to conceal physical pain in front of their peers, is a fear of negative consequences, and that controlling facial behavior is the most common method of regulating expressions of emotion (Zeman & Garber, 1996). This suggests that a child learns to dissimulate pain only in the course of learning the complicated interpersonal use of ‘having pain’ (Wittgenstein, 1982). He must learn not only ‘He has a pain’, but also ‘I think (believe) he has a pain’ and ‘He thinks I have a pain’ (Wittgenstein, 1980a).

Paper 2: Primitive pain-expression and deliberate control

Description:

Approaches to pain assessment typically distinguish between self-report and nonverbal, observational indices, but do not specify criteria or reasoning for the distinction (Hadjistavropoulos & Craig, 2002). Self-report indicators usually employ verbal report to describe the individual’s pain experience, or to communicate qualities of experience through the use of speech (e.g. ‘I have a dull nagging pain in my lumbar region’). The context is important as the exchange is either initiated by the individual in pain or serves as a response to others’ queries. Observational indicators typically focus upon nonverbal, publicly observable manifestations of pain including facial expressions, cry, limb and torso movements and paralinguistic qualities of speech.

The nonverbal behavior that is the focus of observational indices typically can be viewed as primitive in the sense that the behavior represents reflexive patterns of response to actual or impending tissue damage that are not anteceded by introspective awareness or inner observation of private phenomena (Wittgenstein, 1958b; 1980b; 1982). For example, babies’ cries typically alert mothers and caretakers as to children’s needs and initiate required care, even though the infant cannot be characterized as intending or consciously understanding the interaction. While pain is a powerful initiator of attention, introspection does not mediate or modulate primitive behavioral reactions. Instead, we claim that when conscious awareness is employed to influence any form of social communication, the expression cannot be taken as an automatic reaction pattern. For example, to pretend to be in pain, an individual must know how a person who is in pain behaves and focus one’s behavior on that model, intend to reproduce it (Wittgenstein, 1982). Moreover, people tend to experience difficulty suppressing nonverbal expressions of pain and there are subtle differences between spontaneous and feigned expressions of pain (Craig et. al, 1999).

Another important aspect of the primitiveness of pain communication pertains to the experience of conscious awareness of what is happening. Self-report indices typically necessitate attention to the task, including some degree of self-observation. By contrast, the behaviors included in many nonverbal indices occur spontaneously without prior awareness, although the individual likely will monitor the display (Hadjistavropoulos & Craig, 2002). This view ignores the important fact that self-report is used as a partial substitute for automatic nonverbal behaviors (Wittgenstein, 1958b). The exclamation ‘It hurts’, the groan ‘I have a stomach-ache’, the cry ‘I’ve hurt myself’ are reflexive patterns of response, not descriptions; they are comparable to automatic nonverbal behaviors rather than to reports such as ‘He has a back-pain’. In this situation, there is no such thing as my ‘finding out’ that I am in pain, or of my ‘attending’ or ‘recognizing’ my pain-sensations or experiences (Wittgenstein, 1958b).

A primitive expression of pain can be over-ridden to some degree. For instance, facial pain expression can be voluntarily controlled, although the upper face is less amenable to conscious control (Rinn, 1984). Communicative acts often reflect anticipation of consequences. As Wittgenstein (1958b) noted, pain behavior is deeply influenced by conditioning and learning. We claim that the more dependent pain behavior is on learning and conditioning, the more it will be subject to deliberate mediation. Empirical evidence suggests that nonverbal pain expressions that are genuine can be distinguished from masked or exaggerated expressions (Hadjistavropoulos et. al, 1996), possibly because of the greater automaticity of nonverbal expression places limits on the degree to which it can be influenced by learning and conditioning (in contrast to self-report). Observers generally appreciate this and communicate preferences for nonverbal behavior over verbal behavior when assessing the truthfulness of others’ pain behavior (Craig, Prkachin, & Grunau, 1992). This suggests that pain assessment presupposes behavioral manifestations, primarily nonverbal and observational indices, and that ascribing pain in others is possible only where we have criteria for identifying pain, which means that pain must be capable of being expressed (Wittgenstein, 1958b). 

Paper 3: The indeterminacy of pain

Description:

Research claims that significant discrepancies exist between self-report, non-verbal expressions of pain, and evidence of tissue damage, reflecting the impact of some of these criteria, in children (Doherty et al., 1993) and in adults (Craig et al., 1992). Prkachin et al. (1994) found that self-report, nonverbal expression and observers’ judgments were in agreement when the pain was severe, but that observers had difficulty judging accurately a sufferer’s inner state when the pain was submaximal, even though evidence was manifest in the face. There is no guarantee that pain expression will be detected by the observer or that the observer will be able to draw accurate conclusions about the state of the sufferer.

It has been suggested that this inconsistency reflects the multidimensional nature of pain and human ability to detect only selected features at any given time (Hadjistavropoulos & Craig, 2002). For example, it is common for clinicians to encounter patients who appear to complain unreasonably, but express minimal nonverbal pain, and the opposite. Prkachin and Craig (1995) propose that as the sufferer’s experience is expressed, there is a loss of information transfer, causing discrepancies between the different pain indices.

In this paper, we propose to understand the relationships among the various indicators of pain by recalling Wittgenstein’s reminder that the word ‘pain’ refers to ‘patterns in the weave of our life’ (Wittgenstein, 1958b), and the complexity of this weave explains why the different pain indices are not always in agreement. It also explains why third-person psychological judgments (e.g. clinical reports) are sometimes uncertain. This reflects an indeterminacy which is constitutive of our concept of pain. That indeterminacy in turn is due to communal patterns of behavior and the complex nature of our form of life: the concept of pain must be flexible and elastic because human behavior, and our reaction to it, is diverse and unpredictable (Wittgenstein, 1980b; 1982; 1992). Given the complexities of the pain experience, it cannot be expected that simple criteria could capture the full range of the experience (Hadjistavropoulos & Craig, 2002; Wittgenstein, 1980b). Hence, the indeterminacy of the pain experience and the challenges associated with characterizing emotional states logically exclude either self-report or nonverbal behavior alone as capable of giving expression to the subtleties involved.

As Wittgenstein (1958b) observes, connections between the sensation of pain and reporting pain are highly context-dependent and depend on the criteria used to judge it (e.g. self-report or observational criteria), who is expressing the self-report (e.g. age, gender), the reasons for expressing the self-report, and the person’s understanding of the consequences of reporting pain. Moreover, there is considerable potential for response bias when self-report is used to communicate features of painful experience to others (Anand & Craig, 1996). Since self-report is a fallible source of data (Schwartz, 1999), nonverbal information (e.g. facial expressions) is often needed and employed for pain assessment (Craig, 1993). Finally, even those who are closely acquainted with a person can make even the most subtle judgments with certainty, without being able to specify conclusive criteria, since their evidence is ‘imponderable’, that is, consists of a complex syndrome of behavior, context and prior events (Wittgenstein, 1958b).

Although the indeterminacy of our concept of pain means that the different pain indices are not typically connected in a rigid way, it is possible to increase sensitivity to pain communicated by facial expression by brief periods of training. Solomon et al. (1997) found that exposure to a 30-minute training video increased sensitivity to subtle facial movements associated with low levels of pain. This lends hope to the possibility of developing a clinical tool to detect pain.

Paper 4: Is there a pain face?

Description:

        Studies using the Facial Action Coding System (FACS; Ekman & Friesen, 1978) reveal a combination of facial expressions that appear to be specific to acute pain and that reveal the connection between pain facial expression and pain (Craig, 1980; Prkachin, 1992; Prkachin and Solomon, 2008). Core action units (AUs) in adults are brow lowering (corrugator: AU 4), cheek raise and lid tighten (both parts of orbicularis oculi: AU6 and 7), nose wrinkle and upper lip-raise (both parts of levator labii: AU 9 and 10), and eye closing (AU43) (Craig et al., 1992). It has been suggested that pain facial expression is a combination of the core actions along with a limited range of other actions; an expression that is better described as an indeterminate set than a fixed prototype (Prkachin & Craig, 1995). In naturalistic settings, we find it easier to describe a person as ‘in pain’ than to describe his facial features or behavior in precise physical terms, and we do not typically infer psychologically relevant descriptions of pain from austere physical ones (Wittgenstein, 1980a, 1992). For we often know the conclusions of such alleged inferences without knowing their premises (Wittgenstein, 1980a).

        Objections to the specificity of the pain face suggest that it forms part of a whole body defensive response to pain, an effort to withdraw from the stimulus and to protect the body. Salzen (2002) claims that pain facial expression consisting of tension in the facial flexor muscles, contraction of the eyes, retraction of the lips, and clenched teeth is part of a general body flexor reaction. This is based on the idea that pain facial expression is a ‘sensory-motor feeling state’, which is ‘aversive’, but separate from secondary distress due to the continuation of pain despite the initial response. Pain facial expression seems to be part of a global flexor contraction of writhing or squirming, which may spill over into the facial musculature (Frijda, 2002; Panksepp and Pasqualini, 2002). One difficulty facing this challenge is that no such whole body behaviors have been described that are specific to pain in humans or in domestic or laboratory animals (Williams, 2002).

        Moreover, given that the face is the primary target of visual attention between humans and provides a dynamic, embodied expression of pain and emotion in human interactions (Cole, 1997, 2001), some justification is required for collapsing pain facial expression into gross motor activity in connection to stimuli (Williams, 2002). Wittgenstein (1958b) makes a related point that if a person has hurt his hand, he may nurse his hand, but we comfort him: ‘…if someone has a pain in his hand, then the hand does not say so (unless it writes it) and one does not comfort the hand, but the sufferer: one looks into his face’ (Wittgenstein, 1958b, §286). It is not the body that is in pain, but the human being. Available evidence shows that the face in pain is highly salient for observers who ranked the eyes the most important feature, followed by brows, eyelids, mouth, head, forehead, and then other body parts (Prkachin et al., 1983).

        Closely related to the question of a specific pain facial expression in the individual is its detection and interpretation by observers. Judgment of pain in another person relies heavily on facial cues: brow lowering, eye blinking, cheek raise, and upper lip raise are used consistently by observers to judge pain in adults and in children (Craig et al., 1991). There is evidence of reasonably accurate identification of pain expression in adults and infants employing these facial cues (e.g., Prkachin et al. 1994).

The overlap between pain and other emotions concerning the activated facial action units, however, challenges the evidence for the detection of the pain face. After all, when people are in pain, their faces may express a blend of emotions including fear, anger, disgust, surprise, and so on, reflecting a ‘fuzzy’ emotional state of distress or discomfort, rather than expressing the specific experience of pain. It does not follow, however, that sharing of AUs across expressions renders observers unable to distinguish anger from fear or sadness. After all, detection and interpretation only have to be effective, not perfect (cf. Wittgenstein, 1958b, §79d). This may support the claim, made earlier, that the pain face expression is accurately described as an indeterminate or ‘fuzzy’ set than a fixed prototype.

Paper 5: Moebius Syndrome and pain catastrophizing

Description:

Pain intensity is strongly connected to the associated sense of danger and avoidance from physical threat (Wittgenstein, 1958b). An individual expressing pain may receive benefit when that expression is followed by protective actions by observers (Craig, 2004). However, pain expression is not merely the function of inner observation or recognition of private experiences (Wittgenstein, 1958b, 1980b, 1982). The interpersonal context may be essential in explaining how and when pain is expressed. The concept of pain is connected to pain behavior in circumstances of tissue damage or pathology (Wittgenstein, 1958b), but also involves diverse social reactions, ranging from supportive or empathic responses to interpersonal distancing and loss of relatedness, punishment, or even exploitation of vulnerability (Williams, 2002). When negative reactions to pain behavior are anticipated, suppression of pain expression might arise (Williams, 2002). In the presence of solicitous others, by contrast, one might expect robust pain expression (Morley et al., 2000).

In those in whom social support is the norm, pain catastrophizing may also occur. This is defined as ‘an exaggerated negative orientation towards actual or anticipated pain experiences’ (Sullivan et al., 1995), and can be a major determinant of the intrapersonal features of pain, including heightened pain intensity, distress and disability (Sullivan et al., 2001). It is also claimed that pain catastrophizing has interpersonal features such that those who catastrophize about pain seek social support by robust expression of pain, because of perceived danger (Sullivan et al., 2006). The presence of others may then function as a discriminative cue for the expression of pain in those who catastrophize about pain.

How social presence affects pain behavior in adults with congenital facial paralysis is unknown. In this paper we report the experiences of social presence on pain expression in adults with Möbius syndrome, and the extent to which it is moderated by any tendency to catastrophize about pain. Due to the various features associated with Möbius syndrome, including facial immobility, interactions with other people can be difficult to achieve and sustain (Briegel, 2006). They are at higher risk of experiencing rejection or lack of reinforcement, especially with unknown others. These experiences can lead to low self-esteem, behavioral problems (e.g., episodic dyscontrol) and even psychiatric disorders (Cole, 1997, 1999, 2001).

In addition to these potential problems with communication of pain, there is also evidence that some with Möbius have altered or reduced emotional experience (Cole and Spalding, 2008). This might also modify their expression of negative experiences like pain. Given these overlapping problems, expression, experience and relatedness to others, we investigated the effects of social presence, emotional experience and pain experience and expression in those with Möbius. This is a rare syndrome and we felt that the best way to approach this initially was through extended narrative, though we have also used well known inventories of emotional experience and pain.

We expected that it may be likely that adults with Möbius would show more pain behavior in the presence of a significant other than in the presence of a stranger, and that this would be most pronounced in adults who frequently catastrophize or exaggerate the threat value of pain sensations. 

Please note: This proposal requires ethical approval.

 

Bibliography

1. Anand, K. J., & Craig, K.D. 1996. New perspectives on the definition of pain. Pain, 67, 3-6.

2. Briegel, W. 2006. Neuropsychiatric findings of Möbius sequence – a review. Clinical Genetics, 70(2), 91-97.

3. Chaves, J.F., Brown, J.M. 1987. Spontaneous cognitive strategies for the control of clinical pain and stress. Journal of Behavioral Medicine, 10, 263-276.

4. Cole, J. 1997. On ‘being faceless’: selfhood and facial embodiment. Journal of Consciousness Studies 4(5-6), 467-484.

5. Cole, J. 1999. About Face. MA: The MIT Press.

6. Cole, J. 2000. Living with difficulties of facial processing: Some ontological consequences of clinical facial problems. Pragmatics and Cognition 8(1), 237-260.

7. Cole, J. 2001. Empathy needs a face. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(5-7), 51-68.

8. Cole, J., Spalding, H. 2008. The Invisible Smile: living without facial expression. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

9. Craig, K. D. 1980. Ontogenetic and cultural influences on the expression of pain in man. In: Pain and society, ed. H.W. Kosterlitz & L.Y. Terenius. Weinheim Verlag Chemie.

10. Craig, K.D. 1993. The facial expression of pain: better than a thousand words? APS Journal, 1, 153-162.

11. Craig, K.D. 2004. Social communication of pain enhances protective functions: a comment on Deyo, Prkachin and Mercer. Pain, 107, 5-6.

12. Craig, K.D., Hill, M.L., & McMustry, B. 1999. Detecting deception and malingering. In A.R. Block, E.F. Kramer & E. Fernandez (Eds.), Handbook of pain syndromes (pp. 41-58). Mahwah: N.J.: Erlbaum.

13. Craig, K.D., Hyde, S.A. & Patrick, C.J. 1991. Genuine, suppressed and faked facial behavior during exacerbation in chronic low back pain. Pain 46, 161-171.

14. Craig, K.D., Prkachin, K.M., and Grunau, R.V.E. 1992. The facial expression of pain. In D.C. Turk and R. Melzack (Eds.), Handbook of Pain Assessment. (pp. 255-274). New York: Guildford Press.

15. Craig, K.D., Whitfield, M.F., Grunau, R.V.E., Linton, J. & Hadjistavropoulos, H.D. 1993. Pain in the preterm neonate: Behavioural and physiological indices. Pain, 52, 287-299.

16. Darwin. C. 1872/1965. The expression of the emotions in man and animals, 3rd edition, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

17. Descartes, R. 1649/1989. The passions of the soul. Indianapolis: Hackett.

18. Doherty, E., Yanni, G., Conroy, R.M. and Bresan, B. 1993. A comparison of child and parent ratings of disability and pain in juvenile chronic arthritis. Journal of Rheumatology, 20, 1563-1566.

19. Ekman, P., & Friesen, W.V. 1978. Facial action coding system. Consulting Psychologists Press.

20. Frijda, N.A. 2002. What is pain facial expression for? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 25, 460.

21. Haberg, G.L. 2002. The Self, Speaking: Wittgenstein, Introspective Utterances, and the Arts of Self-Representation. Revue Internationale de Philosophie 1(219), 9-47.

22. Hagberg, G.L. 2004. The Self, Thinking: Wittgenstein, Augustine, and the Autobiographical Situation, Wittgenstein, Philosophy, and the Arts, ed. P. Lewis. Ashgate, pp. 215-233.

23. Hadjistavropoulos, H.D., Craig, K.D., Hadjistavropoulos, T., & Poole, G.D. 1996. Subjective judgments of deception in pain expression: Accuracy and errors. Pain, 73, 251-258.

24. Hadjistavropoulos, T., & Craig, K.D. 2002. A theoretical framework for understanding self-report and observational measures of pain: a communications model. Behaviour Research and Therapy, 40, 551-570.

25. Kumar, D. 1990. Moebius syndrome. Journal of Medical Genetics, 27, 18-26.

26. Larchoette, A.C., Chambers, C.T., Craig, K.D. 2006. Genuine, suppressed and faked expressions of pain in children. Pain, 126, 64-71.

27. Libow, J.A. 2000. Child and adolescent illness falsification. Pediatrics, 105, 336-342.

28. Merskey, H., & Bogduk, N (eds.). 1994. Classification of Chronic Pain, Second Edition, IASP Task Force on Taxonomy.

29. Morley, S., Doyle, K., and Besse, A. 2000. Talking to others about pain: suffering in silence. In: M. Devor, M.C. Rowbottom and Z. Wiesenfeld-Hallin, Editors, Proceedings of the 9th world congress on pain, progress in pain research and management, vol. 16, IASP, Seattle, pp. 1123-1129.

30. Panksepp, J., & Pasqualini, M, S. 2002. “Mindscoping” pain and suffering. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 25, 468.

31. Prkachin, K.M. 1992. The consistency of facial expressions of pain: A comparison across modalities. Pain 51, 297-306.

32. Prkachin, K.M., Berzins, S. & Mercer, S.R. 1994. Encoding and decoding of pain expressions: A judgment study. Pain 58, 253-259.

33. Prkachin, K.M., & Craig, K.D. 1995. Expressing pain: the communication and interpretation of facial pain signals. Journal of Nonverbal Behavior, 19 (4), 191-205.

34. Prkachin, K.M., Currie, N.A., & Craig, K.D. 1983. Judging nonverbal expression of pain. Canadian Journal of Behavioral Science 15, 409-421.

35. Prkachin, K.M., Solomon, P.E. 2008. The structure, reliability and validity of pain expression: Evidence from patients with shoulder pain. Pain: in press, corrected proof.

36. Rinn, W.E. 1984. The neuropsychology of facial expression: A review of the neurological and psychological mechanisms for producing facial expressions. Psychological Bulletin, 95, 52-77.

37. Rosenstiel, A.K., Keefe, F.J. 1983. The use of coping strategies in chronic low back pain patients: relationship to patient characteristics and current adjustment. Pain, 17, 33-44.

38. Salzen, E.A. 2002. The feeling of pain and the emotion of distress. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 25, 471.

39. Schwartz, N. 1999. Self-reports: How the questions shape the answers. American Psychologist, 54, 93-105.

40. Solomon, P.E., Prkachin, K.M., Farewell, V. 1997. Enhancing sensitivity to facial expression of pain. Pain, 71, 279-284.

41. Spanos, N.P., Radtke-Bodorik, H.L., Ferguson, J.D., et al., The effects of hynotic susceptibility, suggestions for analgesia, and utilization of cognitive strategies on the reduction of pain. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 88, 282-292.

42. Stevens, B.J., Johnston, C.C. & Horton, L. 1994. Factors that influence the behavioural pain responses of premature infants. Pain, 59, 101-109.

43. Sullivan, M.J.L., Bishop, S.R., & Pivik, J. 1995. The Pain Catastrophizing Scale: development and validation. Psychological Assessment, 7, 524-532.

44. Sullivan, M.J.L., Thorn, B., Haythornthwaite, J., Keefe, F., Martin, M., Bradley, L., et al. 2001. Theoretical perspectives on the relation between cattastrophizing and pain. Clinical Journal of Pain, 17, 52-64.

45. Sullivan, M.J.L., Martel, M.O., Tripp, D.A., Savard, A., Crombez, G. 2006. The relation between catastrophizing and the communication of the pain experience. Pain, 122, 282-288.

46. Sullivan, M.D. 2001. Finding pain between minds and bodies. The Clinical Journal of Pain, 17(2), 146-156.

47. Turk, D.C., & Rudy, T.E. 1992. Cognitive factors and persistent pain: a glimpse into Pandora’s box. Cognitive Therapy Research, 16, 99-122.

48. Wierzbicka, A. 2000. The semantics of human facial expressions. Pragmatics and Cognition 8(1), 147-183.

49. Wierzbicka, A. 1999. Emotions across Languages and Cultures: Diversity and Universals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

50. Williams, Amanda C. de C. 2002. Facial expression of pain: An evolutionary account. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 25, 439-488.

51. Wittgenstein, L. 1958. The Blue and Brown Books. Oxford: Blackwell.

52. Wittgenstein, L. 1958b. Philosophical Investigations. ed. G.E.M. Anscombe and R.Rhees. tr. G.E.M. Anscombe, 2nd edition. Oxford: Blackwell.

53. Wittgenstein, L. 1967. Zettel. ed. G.E.M. Anscombe and G.H. von Wright, tr. G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell.

54. Wittgenstein, L. 1969. On Certainty. ed. G.E.M. Anscombe and G.H. von Wright, tr. D. Paul and G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell.

55. Wittgenstein, L. 1980a. Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology, Volume I, ed. G.E.M. Anscombe and G.H. von Wright, tr. G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell.

56. Wittgenstein, L. 1980b. Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology, Volume II, ed. G.H. von Wright and H. Nyman, tr. C.G. Luckhart and M.A.E. Aue. Oxford: Blackwell.

57. Wittgenstein, L. 1982. Last Writings on the Philosophy of Psychology, Volume I, ed. G.H. von Wright and H. Nyman, tr. C.G. Luckhart and M.A.E. Aue. Oxford: Blackwell.

58. Wittgenstein, L. 1992. Last Writings on the Philosophy of Psychology, Volume II, ed. G.H. von Wright and H. Nyman, tr. C.G. Luckhart and M.A.E. Aue. Oxford: Blackwell.

59. Zeman, J., Garber, J. 1996. Display rules for anger, sadness, and pain: it depends on who is watching. Child Development, 67, 957-973.

 

 

The International Wittgenstein Conference in Taiwan will take place on November 7-8, 2008, in Taipei City, Taiwan, with the support of the Logic, Mind and Methodology (LMM) Group of the Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University. 

This conference is proudly associated with the 80th Anniversary celebrations of National Taiwan University. 

List of Presenters 

Kai-Yuan Cheng
Department of Philosophy, National Chung Cheng University, Taiwan
A New Look at the Skeptical Solution of Rule-Following: Lessons from a Generic Study

Leo Cheung
Baptist University of Hong Kong, Hong Kong
The Tractatus and the Problem of the Unity of the Proposition

Byron Kaldis
Hellenic Open University, Greece
Wittgenstein’s Tractatus: Logical Scaffolding and Formal Ontology

David MacArthur
University of Sydney, Australia
Is Wittgenstein an Expressivist?

David McCarty
Indiana University, USA
Rule-following and Other Fallacies

Michael Mi
Soochow University, Taiwan
Climbing Ladders or Following Rules

Eric Oberheim
Humboldt University, Germany
Wittgenstein and Feyerabend

Nico Orlandi
Rice University, USA
Aspect-Seeing: Wittgenstein and Explanation in Psychology

Marcelo Stamm
University of Tasmania, Australia
Wittgenstein’s Topology: The Seat of the Soul

Simon van Rysewyk
Shih Hsin University, Taiwan
Wittgenstein and the consequences of facial paralysis

Christian Wenzel
National Chi Nan University, Taiwan
Wittgenstein and Meaning Blindness

Daniel Whiting
University of Southampton, UK
The Normativity of Meaning Defended

Jeu-Jenq Yuann
National Taiwan University, Taiwan
Wittgenstein and Popper on the Idea of Negation

Feng-Wei Wu
Post-Doctoral Research Fellow, National Science Council, Taiwan
Making up as We Go along-Wittgenstein and Ethics

The IWCT webpage is here.

The difficulty of philosophy, Wittgenstein once suggested, is knowing when to stop.

The question ‘What is philosophy?’ can itself be questioned, and these question marks in turn can be scutinzed for their appeal and suitability, and so on. It might be asked, for instance, why the subject should be represented in necessary and sufficient conditions; conditions coupled to some metaphysical object hovering tantilizingly above our heads – a thing which no one sees, but which we think is not entirely imperceptible. This question may appeal to some philosophers, others not, while it may repel some in the strongest sense. What one conceives the subject to be is more often than not a question of personal temperament, of ‘how things are settled in me’.

In any event, there are as many conceptions of philosophy as there are philosophers, which may be a clue, for in practice the subject lacks the formal unity of the sciences.  Whatever else we conceive it to be, philosophy is thoroughly interrogative, which may not in itself be a terribly illuminating thing to say, except that when we remember that a philosopher is someone who primarily thinks the question, not the answer to the question. For it is of course a further question what an ‘answer’ to a philosophical question can be or looks like, what face it presents to our searching eyes, how to take it in, or even what to do with it tomorrow. And the great lack of consensus among philosophers, which is typical in most philosophical discussions, certainly complicates matters even more.

Wittgenstein also said, autobiographically, that a philosopher is a citizen of no community in particular. Well, that simply goes for him. And others like him (Nietzsche). In my humble view, philosophy can be a joy. And the joy of it lies in the valued membership others grant me as part of an intellectual community of like-minded individuals, who form my philosophical millieu, and with whom I exchange and above all share questions, points of view, scraps of logic, remembrances, distant visions and lost horizons.  The sharing of it all is key, I believe. But, why?

October 2008
M T W T F S S
 12345
6789101112
13141516171819
20212223242526
2728293031  

Blog Stats

  • 359,987 hits